In the midst of several important and historic rulings by
the Supreme Court this term (Voting Rights Act, DOMA), a ruling pertaining to
the Indian Child Welfare Act (ICWA) has been less remarked upon. I think this ruling is similarly important
and historic, so here is my take on it.
First, a brief synopsis (you can see a timeline here). The case involves a baby girl, Veronica, born
to a Latina mother and Cherokee father in September of 2009 in Oklahoma. The parents’ relationship ended a few months
before she was born and her mother, through an adoption attorney, was connected
with a white family, the Copabiancos, who wanted to adopt Veronica. The adoption attorney contacted the Cherokee
nation about the father’s membership in the tribe, but due to errors in the
information about the father, they were unable to verify his membership. A few days after Veronica was born, the Copabiancos
filed to adopt Veronica and have her moved to their home in South
Carolina. The courts granted this
request on the basis of paperwork that listed Veronica as “Hispanic.” Several months later in January, 12 days
before the father was deployed to Iraq, the Copabiancos attorney served him
with papers relinquishing his rights to Veronica. He claimed he thought the papers were
relinquishing ties with the mother and requested to have them back after he
signed. The process server refused. The father then contacted a JAG lawyer for
advice and, a few days later, filed documentation to establish paternity,
custody, and support of Veronica (this is about 4 months after Veronica’s
birth). At this point, the Cherokee
Nation verified his membership while Veronica remained with the Copabiancos
(but was never officially adopted, only granted temporary custody). In May the father filed a response in family
court stating he did not consent to the adoption. The father returned from Iraq, in December of
2010, and a family court trial finally occurred in September of 2011. In November, the family court denied the
Copabiancos’ petition for adoption and awarded custody to the father, stating
that ICWA applies to the case. The court
further noted there was no reason to terminate the father’s parental rights or
to think Veronica would not be safe and cared for with him. After a series of appeals, the case was heard
by the Supreme Court who ruled that ICWA did not apply in this case because the
father did not have custody of the child when she was first adopted and because
no relatives or other Native Americans came forward to adopt Veronica (thus
they could not be given preference).
The Supreme Court sent the case back to the South Carolina Supreme
court which allowed the Copabiancos to adopt Veronica on July 17th,
2013. Once the requirements of ICWA were
found to not apply, the South Carolina Supreme Court returned to a ruling based
on South Carolina law that the father did not have to consent to Veronica’s
adoption because he was not living with the mother for a continuous period of
six months before the adoption and did not pay child support or expenses
relating to the pregnancy and birth. Thus, they allowed the Copabiancos to
adopt. In addition, although the South Carolina Supreme Court could have
required a “best interests” hearing to decide about the final adoption, they
choose not to do so in order to bring the case to a resolution more quickly
(family courts are horribly slow). [If
this had been done, the family court’s finding that he was a fit parent and his
18 months of care for her could have been taken into account.]
This case raises some important issues about tribal sovereignty
and weakens the original intent of ICWA.
I’ll get to that in a minute. When
I first read about this case, the thing that struck me was that this father’s
situation seemed pretty typical and representative of the way fathers are treated
by the child welfare systems. The majority
opinion held that the father “abandoned” his child and therefore did not
deserve the protections afforded by ICWA.
Only if one narrowly focuses on the paperwork he signed relinquishing
his rights, something he seems to have been ill informed about and to have immediately
regretted, does it seem he abandoned her.
That the court could do so is also related to the common standards for
retaining parental rights that are applied to men: marriage or cohabitation
with the mother and payment of child support (this is the law in South
Carolina). The courts should have, I think, taken into account the larger circumstances
and his later behavior, but they did not do so.
This highlights the problems with this narrow way of determining
parental rights, especially in cases involving fathers who might be unable to
meet these criteria but still wish to parent.
In my research on child welfare in New York City, I was
often struck by how easy it was to erase a father’s presence or potential
presence in a child’s life and that a termination of parental rights, for a
father, was generally a quick and very smooth process. Granted, in many cases fathers are not
present and thus it makes sense to focus on the mother, the only
caretaker. At the same time, I found
that many fathers were systematically disadvantaged by child welfare casework
practice and the assumptions that underlie it.
Ideologies about proper and fit caretaking are profoundly shaped by
race, gender, and class. Women were
automatically mothers by virtue of giving birth whereas fathers had to provide
for a child to be taken seriously as a father.
It was also assumed that poor men of color would not be fit caretakers. Although
the courts must present evidence of unfitness to deny custody, denying custody without
any evidence the father was an unsuitable caretaker happened routinely. For
example, I ran across cases in which a child was removed from a mother due to
her drug use or another problem and placed in foster care with no attempt
whatsoever to determine who the father was and if he could care for the
child. If a father was eventually
notified of the situation and able to contact caseworkers or the courts to
request custody, it would be automatically denied until a full investigation
was conducted of him and his home, even in the absence of any allegations
against him. Although this is partly a
matter of the courts caution and unwillingness to release a child from foster
care unless they feel sure of the child’s safety, I think it goes beyond
this. Caseworkers assumed they would
find something that would disqualify the father. But even before that point, they often
assumed there was, for all practical purposes, not a father at all. The assumption that a father who does not
have direct custody has fewer rights (if any at all) is thus common, and, in
many cases, unfair.
In short, I found that fathers were ignored (as were their
relatives in the case of finding kinship foster homes) and had much more work
to do to convince officials they could care for children. These patterns, that exist in child welfare
more generally, played a role in this case.
Apart from the ways the case will affect Native Americans and the
application of ICWA in the future, I think it will also provide justification
for a common practice of assuming a parent without custody automatically has
fewer rights. In many communities,
Native American and other poor communities of color most notably, it is common
for parents, especially fathers, to not have direct custody at one time or
another due to a complex combination of circumstances, many of which they have
little control over. Thus, I think this
ruling is a blow to many parents struggling to raise children with few
resources or in communities in which children are regularly placed in foster
care.
Apart from the ways in which this case demonstrates general
problems with child welfare practice with regard to fathers and their parental
rights, this case is important in how it will affect tribal sovereignty. The
original intent behind ICWA was to provide added protections for Native
American tribes and families and to deal with the pervasive problem of Native
American children being raised away from their families and tribes leading to
the profound loss of language and culture (more background can be found here). The law recognized the devastating effects of
Indian boarding schools (which explicitly were about socializing native
children to be more “white”) and the pervasive practice of placing children
with white foster and adoptive families.
Thus, it set minimum standards for handling these cases (including
higher standards for terminating parental rights; a clear preference for
placing Native American children with family, other tribal members, and other
Native Americans; the preference for tribal authorities to handle child
protection cases). The law is explicitly not only about protecting Native
American individuals and families from discriminatory practices, it is also
about the rights of Native American tribes to govern their own affairs and
protect the continued existence of their cultures. In enacting ICWA, Congress found that “there
is no resource that is more vital to the continued existence and integrity of
Indian tribes than their children. ...” Congress also determined that states
“...often failed to recognize the essential tribal relations of Indian people
and the cultural and social standards prevailing in Indian communities and
families.” (http://www.tribal-institute.org/lists/chapter21_icwa.htm).
ICWA was supposed to ensure these concerns were taken into account.
Rather than respecting the right of the Cherokee Nation to
play a key role in handling the case of a Cherokee father and his daughter, the
court focused narrowly on the father’s actions and the lack of a Native
adoptive couple when the child was born. [It is unclear to me why the fact that
the adoption attorney provided incorrect information to the Cherokee Nation (in
addition to the fact the father was fighting for custody) was not considered an
adequate explanation for why no other family members or other Native Americans
sought custody.] Carving out an
exception to tribal control when a Native American parent does not have custody
is a problem since these situations are not uncommon).
Although the courts’ opinion was not far reaching and did not find ICWA
unconstitutional, I think it does set a precedent that limits the reach of the
act and undermines one of its most important purposes—protecting the rights of
Native American groups.
Finally, I think this case raises an interesting issue
regarding race in the U.S. Significantly, the ruling begins with the statement:
“This case is about a little girl who is classified as an Indian because she is
1.2% (3/256) Cherokee.” The implication, I think, is that the child is not “native
enough” to be protected by the law. This
statement is important in the ideology of race that underlies it. It assumes that race is determined by blood
and percentage of blood, a common American racial construct. This is not how the Cherokee people define
being Cherokee, however. For them, the criterion is being a direct descendant
of a Cherokee ancestor. According to the
Cherokee Nation Veronica simply IS Cherokee.
Although this might seem like a small matter, the court's statement
betrays a subtle disregard for the Cherokee Nation’s ability to define who is
and is not Cherokee.
It is interesting to me that defining race by percentage of “Indian blood” here becomes a way to subtly limit tribal sovereignty, while ideas about ancestry and blood quantum have often been used in an opposite way with regards to African Americans historically. The rule of “hypodescent” or the “one-drop rule” has been used to define anyone with any black ancestors as black in an effort to keep a clear color-line between white and black. This creates a kind of caste system in which “escape” through intermarriage or “passing” is limited. In other words, the idea that race is biological and about “blood” can be used in different ways as convenient for those with more power and privilege in a racialized social system. [As an aside this is interesting to think about in the George Zimmerman case where he was sometimes defined as “white” and thus respectable and law abiding while at others his “Latino” heritage was emphasized to argue he was not racist.]
It is interesting to me that defining race by percentage of “Indian blood” here becomes a way to subtly limit tribal sovereignty, while ideas about ancestry and blood quantum have often been used in an opposite way with regards to African Americans historically. The rule of “hypodescent” or the “one-drop rule” has been used to define anyone with any black ancestors as black in an effort to keep a clear color-line between white and black. This creates a kind of caste system in which “escape” through intermarriage or “passing” is limited. In other words, the idea that race is biological and about “blood” can be used in different ways as convenient for those with more power and privilege in a racialized social system. [As an aside this is interesting to think about in the George Zimmerman case where he was sometimes defined as “white” and thus respectable and law abiding while at others his “Latino” heritage was emphasized to argue he was not racist.]
No comments:
Post a Comment